11 April 2025

Why Quantum Mechanics is Currently Wrong and How to Fix It.

It is now almost a century since "quantum mechanics" became established as the dominant paradigm for thinking about the structure and motion of matter on the nanoscale. And yet the one thing quantum mechanics cannot do is explain what it purports to describe. Sure, quantum mechanics can predict the probability of measurements. However, no one knows how it does this. 

Presently, no one understands the foundations of quantum mechanics

Feynman's quote to this effect is still accurate. It has recently been restated by David Deutsch, for example:

"So, I think that quantum theory is definitely false. I think that general relativity is definitely false." (t = 1:16:13)
"Certainly, both relativity and quantum theory are extremely good approximations in the situations where we want to apply them... So, yes, certainly, good approximations for practical purposes, but so is Newton's theory. That's also false." (t = 1:28:35)
—David Deutsch on Sean Carroll's podcast.

I listened to these striking comments again recently. This time around, I realised that my conception of quantum field theory (QFT) was entirely wrong. I have a realistic picture in my head, i.e. when I talk about "waves", something is waving. This is not what GFT says at all. The "fields" in question are entirely abstract. What is waving in quantum mechanics is the notion of the probability of a particle appearing at a certain location within the atom. Below I will show that this thinking is incoherent. 

There have been numerous attempts to reify the quantum wavefunction. And they all lead to ridiculous metaphysics. Some of the most hilarious metaphysics that quantum mechanics has produced are:

  1. The universe behaves one way when we look at it, and a completely different way when we don't.
  2. The entire universe is constantly, and instantaneously, splitting into multiple copies of itself, each located in exactly the same physical space, but with no connections between the copies.
  3. Electrons are made of waves of probability that randomly collapse to make electrons into real particles for a moment.

None of these ideas is remotely compatible with any of the others. And far from there being a consensus, the gaps between "interpretations" are still widening. Anyone familiar with my work on the Heart Sutra will recognise this statement. It's exactly what I said about interpretations of the Heart Sutra.

Physics has lost its grip on reality. It has a schizoid ("splitting") disorder. I believe I know why.


What Went Wrong?

The standard quantum model embraces wave-particle duality as a fundamental postulate. In the 1920s, experiments seemed to confirm this. This is where the problems start.

Schiff's (1968) graduate-level textbook, Quantum Mechanics, discusses the idea that particles might be considered "wave packets":

The relation (1.2) between momentum and wavelength, which is known experimentally to be valid for both photons and particles, suggests that it might be possible to use concentrated bunches of waves to describe localized particles of matter and quanta of radiation. To fix our ideas, we shall consider a wave amplitude or wave function that depends on the space coordinates x, y, z and the time t. This quantity is assumed to have three basic properties. First, it can interfere with itself, so that it can account for the results of diffraction experiments. Second, it is large in magnitude where the particle or photon is likely to be and small elsewhere. And third, will be regarded as describing the behavior of a single particle or photon, not the statistical distribution of a number of such quanta. (Schiff 1968: 14-15. Emphasis added)

I think this statement exemplifies the schizoid nature of quantum mechanics. The Schrödinger model begins with a particle, described as a "wave packet", using the mathematics of waves. The problem is that physicists still want to use the wave equation to recover the "position" or "momentum" of the electron in the atom, as though it is a particle. I have seen people dispute that this was Schrödinger's intention, but it's certainly how Schiff saw it, and his text was widely respected in its day.

The obvious problem is that, having modelled the electron as a wave, how do we then extract from it information about particles, such as position and momentum? Mathematically, the two ideas are not compatible. Wave-talk and particle-talk cannot really co-exist. 

In fact, Schrödinger was at a loss to explain this. It was Max Born who pointed out that if you take the modulus squared value of the wave function (which outputs complex-numbered vectors), you get a probability distribution that allows you to predict measurements. As I understand it, Schrödinger did not like this at all. In an attempt to discredit this approach, he formulated his classic thought experiment of the cat in the box. A polemic that failed so badly, that the Copenhagen crowd adopted Schrödinger's cat as their mascot. I'll come back to this.

However, there is a caveat here. No one has ever measured the position of an electron in an atom, and no one ever will. It's not possible. We have probes that can map out forces around atoms, but we don't have a probe that we, say, can stick into an atom and wait for the electron to run into it. This is not how things work on this scale.


Can We Do Better? (Yes We Can!)

Electric charge is thought to be a fundamental property of matter. We visualise the electric charge of a proton as a field of electric potentials with a value at every point in space, whose amplitude drops off as the square of the distance. The electric field around a proton is observed to be symmetrical in three dimensions. In two dimensions, a proton looks something like this with radiating, evenly spaced field lines:

An electron looks the same, but the arrows point inwards (the directionality of charge is purely conventional). So if the electron were a point charge, an atom would be an electric dipole, like this:

This diagram shows that if the electron were a point mass/charge, the hydrogen atom would be subject to unbalanced forces. Such an atom would be unstable. Moreover, a moving electric dipole causes fluctuations in the magnetic field that would rapidly bleed energy away from the atom, so if it didn't collapse instantaneously, it would collapse rapidly. 

Observation shows atoms to be quite stable. So, at least in an atom, an electron cannot be a point mass/charge. And therefore, in an atom, an electron is not a point mass/charge.

Observed also shows that hydrogen atoms are electrically neutral. Given that the electric field of the proton is symmetrical in three dimensions, there is only one shape the electron could be and balance the electric charge. A sphere with the charge distributed evenly over it.


The average radius of the sphere would be the estimated value of the atomic radius. Around 53 picometers (0.053 nanometers) for hydrogen. The radius of a proton is estimated to be on the order of 1 femtometer.

Niels Bohr had a similar idea. He proposed that the electron formed a "cloud" around the nucleus. And this cloud was later identified as "a cloud of probability". Which is completely meaningless. The emperor is not wearing any clothes. As David Albert says on Sean Carroll's podcast:

“… there was just this long string of brilliant people who would spend an hour with Bohr, their entire lives would be changed. And one of the ways in which their lives were changed is that they were spouting gibberish that was completely beneath them about the foundations of quantum mechanics for the rest of their lives…” (emphasis added)

We can do better, with some simple logic. We begin by postulating, along with GFT, that the electron is some kind of wave. 

If the electron is a wave, AND the electron is a sphere, AND the atom is stable, AND the atom is electrically neutral, then the electron can only be a spherical standing wave.

Now, some people may say, "But this is exactly what Schrödinger said". Almost. There is a crucial difference. In this model, the spherical standing wave is the electron. Or, looked at from the other direction, an electron (in a hydrogen atom) is a physical sphere with an average radius of ~53 pm. There is no particle, we've logically ruled out particles.

What does observation tell us about the shape of atoms? We have some quite recent data on this. For example, as reported by Lisa Grossman (2013) for New Scientist, here are some pictures of a hydrogen atom recently created by experimenters.

The original paper was in Physical Review.

Sadly, the commentary provided by Grossman is the usual nonsense. But just look at these pictures. The atom is clearly a sphere in reality, just as I predicted using simple logic. Many crafty experiments, have reported the same result. It's not just that the probability function is spherical. Atoms are spheres. Not solid spheres, by any means, but spheres nonetheless.

We begin to part ways with the old boys. And we are instantly in almost virgin territory. To the best of my knowledge, no one has ever considered this scenario before (I've been searching the literature).

The standard line is that the last input classical physics had was Rutherford's planetary model proposed in 1911, after he successfully identified that atoms have a nucleus, which contains most of the mass of the atom. This model was debunked by Bohr in 1913. And classical physics has nothing more to say. As far as any seems to know, "classical physics says the electron is a point mass". No one has ever modelled the electron in an atom as a real wave. At least no one I can find.

This means that there are no existing mathematical models I can adapt to my purpose. I have to start with the general wave equation and customise it to fit. Here is the generalised wave equation of a spherical standing wave:


Where r is the radius of the sphere, θ and φ are angles, and t = time. Notice that it is a second-order partial differential equation, and that the rates of change in each quantity are interdependent. It can be solved, but it is not easy.

The fact is that, while this approach is not identical to existing quantum formalism, it is isomorphic (i.e. has the same form). Once we clarify the concept and what we are trying to do with it, the existing formalism ought to be able to be adapted. So we don't have to abandon quantum mechanics, we just have to alter our starting assumptions and allow that to work through what we have to date. 

An important question arises: What about the whole idea of wave-particle duality?

In my view, any particle-like behaviour is a consequence of experimental design. Sticking with electrons, we may say that every electron detector relies on atoms in the detector absorbing electrons. And there are no fractional electrons. Each electron is absorbed by one and only one atom. It is this phenomenon that causes the appearance of discrete "particle-like" behaviour. At the nano-scale, any scientific apparatus is inevitably an active part of the system.

The electron is a wave. It is not a particle. 

Given the wild success of quantum mechanics (electronics, lasers, and so on), why would anyone want to debunk it? For me, it is because it doesn't explain anything. I didn't get into science so I could predict measurements, by solving abstract maths problems. I got into it so I could understand the world. Inj physics maths is supposed to represent the world and to have a physical interpretation. I'm not ready to give up on that.


The Advantages of Modelling the Electron as a (Real) Wave.

While they are sometimes reported as special features of quantum systems, the fact is that all standing waves have some characteristic features.

In all standing waves, energy is quantised. This is because a standing wave only allows whole numbers of wavelengths. We may use the example of a guitar string that vibrates in one dimension*.

*Note that if you look at a real guitar string, you will see that it vibrates in two dimensions: perpendicular to the face of the guitar and parallel to it.

The ends of the string are anchored. So the amplitude of any wave is always zero at the ends; they cannot move at all. The lowest possible frequency is when the wavelength equals the string length.

The next lowest possible frequency is when the wavelength equals half the string length. And so on.


This generalises. All standing waves are quantised in this way. This is "the music of the spheres". 

Now, spherical standing waves, with a central attractive force exist and were described ca 1782 by Pierre-Simon Laplace. These entities are mathematically very much more complicated than a string vibrating in one dimension. Modelling this is a huge challenge. 

For the purposes of this essay, we can skip to the end and show you what the general case of harmonics of a spherical standing wave looks like when the equations are solved and plotted on a graph.


Anyone familiar with physical chemistry will find these generalised shapes familiar. These are the theoretical shapes of electron orbitals for hydrogen. And this is without any attempt to account for the particular situation of an electron in an atom (the coulomb potential, the electric field interfering with itself, etc).

So not only is the sphere representing the electron naturally quantised, but the harmonics give us electron "orbitals". And, if we drop the idea of the electron as a particle, this all comes from within a classical framework (though not Rutherford's classical framework). 


Why Does Attempting to Reify Probability Lead to Chaos?

As already noted, Schrödinger tried and failed to relate his equation back to reality. Max Born discovered that the modulus squared of the wavefunction vector at a given point could be interpreted as the probability of finding the "the electron" (qua particle) at that point. This accurately predicts the probable behaviour of an electron, though not its actual behaviour. But all this requires electrons to be both waves and point-mass particles. 

Since the real oscillations I'm describing are isomorphic with the notional oscillations predicted by Schrödinger, we can intuit that if we were to try to quantify the probability of the amplitude of the (real) spherical standing wave at a certain point around the sphere, then any probability distribution we created from this would also be isomorphic with application of the Born rule to Schrödinger's equation.

What I've just done, in case it wasn't obvious, is explain the fundamentals of quantum mechanics (in philosophical terms at least) in one sentence. The predicted probabilities take the form that they do because of a physical mechanism: a spherical standing wave. And I have not done any violence to the notion of "reality" in the process. To my knowledge, this has not been done before, although I'm certainly eager to learn if it has.

However, the isomorphism is only causal in one direction. You can never get from a probability distribution to a physical description. Let me explain why by using a simple analogy that can be generalised.

Let's take the very familiar and simple case of a system in which I toss a coin in the air and, when it lands, I note which face is up. The two possible outcomes are heads H and tails T. The probabilities are well-known:

P(H) = 0.5 and P(T) = 0.5.

And as always, the sum of the probabilities of all the outcomes is 1.0. So:

P(H) + P(T) = 1.0

No matter what values we assign to P(H) and P(T), they have to add up to 1.

In physical terms, this means that if we toss 100 coins, we expect to observe heads 50 times and tails 50 times. In practice, we will most likely not get exactly 50 of each because probabilities do not determine outcomes. Still, the more times we toss the coins, the closer our actual distribution will come to the expected value.

Now imagine that I have tossed a coin, it has landed, but I have not yet observed it (call this the one-dimensional Schrödinger's cat, if you like). The standard rhetoric is to say that the coin is in a superposition of two "states". One has to be very wary of the term "state" in this context. Quantum physicists do not use it in the normal way, and it can be very confusing. But I am going to use "state" in a completely naturalistic way. The "state" of the tossed coin refers to which face is up. And it has to be in one of two possible states: H or T.  

Now let's ask what I know and think about what I can know about the coin at this moment before I observe the state of the coin.

I know that the outcome must be H or T. And I know that the odds are 50:50 that it is either one. What else can I know? Nothing. Despite knowing to 100 decimal places what the probability is, I cannot use that information to know what state the coin is in before I observe it. If I start with probabilities, I can say nothing about the fact of the matter (using a phrase David Albert uses a lot). If I reify this concept, I might be tempted to say that there is no fact of the matter

Note also that it doesn't matter if P(H) and P(T) are changing. Let us say that the probabilities change over time and that the change can be precisely described by a function of the coin: Ψ(coin). Are we any better off? Clearly not.

This analogy generalises. No matter how complex my statistical model, no matter how accurately and precisely I know the probability distribution, I still cannot tell you which side up the coin is without looking. There is undoubtedly a physical fact of the matter, but as the old joke goes, you cannot get there from here.

There are an infinite number of reasons why a coin toss will have P(H) = P(T) = 0.5. We can speculate endlessly. This is why the "interpretations" of quantum mechanics are so wildly variable and the resulting metaphysics so counter-intuitive. Such speculations are not bound by the laws of nature. In fact, all such speculations propose radical new laws of nature, like splitting the entire universe in two every time a quantum event happens. 

So the whole project of trying to extract meaningful metaphysics from a probability distribution was wrong-headed from the start. It cannot work, and it does not work. A century of effort by very smart people has not produced any workable ideas. Or any consensus on how to find a workable idea. 


Superposition and the Measurement Problem

The infamous cat experiment, in all its varieties, involves a logical error. As much as Schrödinger resisted the idea, because of his assumption about wave-particle duality, his equation only tells us about the probabilities of states; it does not and cannot tell us which state happens to be the fact of the matter. The information we get from the current formalism is a probability distribution. So the superposition in question is only a superposition of probabilities; it's emphatically not a superposition of states (in my sense). A coin cannot ever be both H and T. That state is not a possible state. 

Is the superposition of probabilities in any way weird? Nope.

The fact that P(H) = 0.5 or P(H) = Ψ(coin) and that P(T) = 0.5 or P(T) = Ψ(coin) are not weird facts. Nor is the fact that P(H) + P(T) = 1. These are common or garden facts, with no mystical implications.

If we grant that the propositions P(H) = 0.5 and P(T) = 0.5 are logically true, then it must also be logically (and mathematically) true to say that P(H) + P(T) = 1. Prior to observations all probabilities coexist at the same time.

For all systems we might meet, all the probabilities for all the outcomes always coexist prior to observing the state of the system. And the probabilities for all but one outcome collapse to zero at the moment we observe the actual state. This is true for any system: coins, cats, electrons, and everything. 

Note also that this is not a collapse of anything physical. No attempt to reify this "collapse" should be made. Probability is an idea we can quantify, but it's not an entity. No existing thing collapses when we observe an event. 

Moreover, Buddhists and hippies take note, our observing an event cannot influence the outcome. Light from the event can only enter our eye after the event has occurred, i.e. only after the probabilities have collapsed. And it takes the brain an appreciable amount of time to register the incoming nerve signal, make sense of it, and present it to the first-person perspective. Observation is always retrospective. So no, observation cannot possibly play any role in determining outcomes. 

One has to remember that probability is abstract. It's an idea about how to quantify uncertainty. Probability is not inherent in nature; it comes from our side of the subject-object divide. Unlike, say, mass or charge, probability is not what a reductionist would call "fundamental". We discover probabilities through observation of long-term trends. At the risk of flogging a dead horse, you cannot start with an abstraction and extract from it a credible metaphysics. Not in the world that we live in. And after a century of trying, the best minds in physics have signally failed in this quixotic endeavour. There is not even a working theory of how to make metaphysics from probabilities. 

The superposition or collapse of probabilities is in no way weird. And this is the only superposition predicted by quantum mechanics. 

In my model, the electron is a wave, and the wave equation that describes it applies at all times. Before, during, and after observation. 

In my model, probabilities superpose when we don't know the facts of the matter, in a completely normal way. It's just that I admit the abstract nature of probability distributions. And I don't try to break reality so that I can reify an abstraction.

On the other hand, my approach is technically classical. A classical approach that ought to predict all the important observations of quantum mechanics, but which can also explain them in physical terms. As such, there is no separation between classical and quantum in my model. It's all classical. And I believe that the implications of this will turn out to be far-reaching and will allow many other inexplicable phenomena to be easily explained.

The so-called measurement problem can be seen as a product of misguided attempts to hypostatise and reify the quantum wavefunction, which only predicts probabilities. It was only ever a problem caused by a faulty conceptualisation of the problem in terms of wave-particle duality. If we drop this obviously false axiom, things will go a lot more smoothly (though the maths is still quite fiendish).

No one ever has or ever will observe a physical superposition. I'm saying that this is because no such thing exists or could exist. It's just nonsense, and we should be brave enough to stand up and say so.

There is no "measurement problem". There's measurement and there is ill-advised metaphysical speculation based on reified abstractions.


What about other quantum weirdness?

I want to keep this essay to a manageable length, so my answer to this question must wait. But I believe that Peter Jackson's (2013) free electron model as a vortex rotating on three axes is perfectly consistent with what I outlined here. And it explains spin very elegantly. If the electron is a sphere in an atom, why not allow it to always be a sphere?

Jackson also elegantly explains why the polarised filter set-up to test Bell's inequalities is not quantum weirdness, but a result of the photon interacting with, and thus being changed by, the filter. At the nano-scale and below, there are no neutral experimental apparatus.

What about interference and the double-slit experiment? Yep, I have some ideas on this as well.

Tunnelling? I confess that I have not tried to account for tunneling just yet. At face value, I think it is likely to turn out to be a case of absorption and re-emission (like Newton's cradle) rather than Star Trek-style teleporting. Again, there is no such thing as a neutral apparatus on the nano-scale or below. If your scientific apparatus is made of matter, it is an active participant in the experiment and at the nano-scale, it changes the outcomes. 

It's time to call bullshit on quantum mechanics and rescue physicists from themselves. After a century of bad metaphysics, let's put the phys back into physics!

~~Φ~~


P.S. My book on the Heart Sutra is coming along. I have a (non-committal) expression of interest from my publisher of choice. I hope to have news to share before the end of 2025.
PPS. I'd quite like to meet a maths genius with some time on their hands...

Bibliography

Grossman, Lisa. (2013). "Smile, hydrogen atom, you're on quantum camera." New Scientist. https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg21829194-900-smile-hydrogen-atom-youre-on-quantum-camera/

Jackson, Peter. (2009). "Ridiculous Simplicity". FQXi. What is Fundamental? https://forums.fqxi.org/d/495-perfect-symmetry-by-peter-a-jackson

Schiff, Leonard I. (1968). Quantum Mechanics. 3rd Ed. McGraw-Hill.

Related Posts with Thumbnails